Scholarly article on topic 'Education as Synesis: A Hermeneutical Contribution to the Pedagogical Theory of Educational Practice'

Education as Synesis: A Hermeneutical Contribution to the Pedagogical Theory of Educational Practice Academic research paper on "Economics and business"

CC BY-NC-ND
0
0
Share paper
OECD Field of science
Keywords
{Philosophy / Education / Synesis / Practice / Hermeneutics}

Abstract of research paper on Economics and business, author of scientific article — Emanuele Isidori

Abstract Synesis, a category mentioned by Aristotle in the sixth book of his Nicomachean Ethics, is, along with phronesis, a fundamental concept of ethics as a human reflection on moral action. Through a hermeneutical methodological approach, this paper will demonstrate how synesis, a concept scarcely studied by scholars in the context of pedagogy and philosophy of education, represents a basic category both of pedagogical epistemology and educational practice, upon which one needs to reflect in order to understand the function and meaning of education and learning in a human perspective.

Academic research paper on topic "Education as Synesis: A Hermeneutical Contribution to the Pedagogical Theory of Educational Practice"

Available online at www.sciencedirect.com

ScienceDirect

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 197 (2015) 531 - 536

7th World Conference on Educational Sciences, (WCES-2015), 05-07 February 2015, Novotel

Athens Convention Center, Athens, Greece

Education as Synesis: A Hermeneutical Contribution to the Pedagogical Theory of Educational Practice

Emanuele Isidoria*

aUniversity of Rome "Foro Italico", Piazza L. De Bosis, 15, Rome 00135, Italy

Abstract

Synesis, a category mentioned by Aristotle in the sixth book of his Nicomachean Ethics, is, along with phronesis, a fundamental concept of ethics as a human reflection on moral action. Through a hermeneutical methodological approach, this paper will demonstrate how synesis, a concept scarcely studied by scholars in the context of pedagogy and philosophy of education, represents a basic category both of pedagogical epistemology and educational practice, upon which one needs to reflect in order to understand the function and meaning of education and learning in a human perspective.

© 2015TheAuthors.Published by ElsevierLtd.This is an open access article under the CC BY-NC-ND license (http://creativecommons.Org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/).

Peer-review under responsibility of Academic World Education and Research Center.

Keywords: Philosophy, Education, Synesis, Practice, Hermeneutics_

1. Introduction

In the sixth book of Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle introduces the concept of synesis without offering any explicit and deep analysis. Educationists know well this chapter, because it speaks about phronesis, which, understood as an intellectual virtue combined with moral virtue and referred to sophia as an intrinsic reference model, is a form of practical knowledge aimed at deliberating and prescribing actions that are good from an ethical point of view. However, the concept "synesis", usually translated as "understanding", "consciousness", "care", "intelligence", or "judgment", is overlooked and scarcely studied (or ignored) in both pedagogy and the philosophy of education.

Thus, on the one hand, phronesis, understood as a practical reason that guides educators' actions and allows them to act and play their functions in the best possible way and with full and appropriate knowledge of the facts, has been largely analyzed and studied in the philosophy of education, and has become part of the conceptual lexicon of this discipline. On the other hand, synesis has never been linked to educational practice.

This being so, the purpose of this study is to demonstrate, through a hermeneutical methodology, not only that the

* Emanuele Isidori. Tel.: +39-06-36733359; fax: +39-06-36733359. E-mail address: labopedagogia@gmail.com

1877-0428 © 2015 The Authors. Published by Elsevier Ltd. This is an open access article under the CC BY-NC-ND license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/).

Peer-review under responsibility of Academic World Education and Research Center. doi:10.1016/j.sbspro.2015.07.183

concept of synesis is closely linked to phronesis, but also that it is fundamental to the philosophical theorizing of education and its epistemology. This study wants to highlight the relevance of synesis and its role in defining the theory of educational work, because this Greek concept helps us better grasp the meaning of key terms in education, understood as a human practice, such as "comprehension", "care", "interest in the other person", and "love for the other".

2. The concept of synesis in Aristotle

In the above-mentioned sixth book of Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle says the following regarding synesis (1143a 1-18; Crisp, 2004):

"Judgement (synesis), that is good judgement (eusynesia), in virtue of which people are said to have judgement or good judgement, is not the same as knowledge in general, or the same as belief (since then everyone would have been a person of judgement); nor is it any one of the particular sciences, such as medicine, which has health as its concern, or geometry, which has spatial dimensions. Judgement is concerned not with what is eternal and unchanging, nor with what comes into being, but with what someone might puzzle and deliberate about. For this reason it is concerned with the same things as practical wisdom (phronesis)." (1-6).

The Stagirite goes on and says:

"But judgement (synesis) and practical wisdom (phronesis) are not the same. Practical wisdom gives commands, since its end is what should or should not be done, while judgement only judges (kritike). Judgement and good judgement (eusynesia) are the same, as are those with judgement and those with good judgement. Judgement, then, is neither the possession nor the acquisition of practical wisdom (phronesis). But just as understanding (manthanein) is called judging (synienai), when one employs scientific knowledge (episteme), so we also call judging (synienai) what is involved in employing belief (doxa) to judge (krinein) what someone else says (allou legontos) about what concerns practical wisdom (phronesis) (and it must judge it nobly (kalos), since judging it well (eu) is the same as judging it nobly (kalos)." (7-15).

And, then, he concludes:

"From his use of the word "judgement" (synesis) in the case of understanding (synienai) is derived the sense in virtue of which people are described as having good judgement (eusynetoi), since we often say that understanding (manthanein) is judging (synienai)." (16-18).

For Liddell and Scott (1996: 1712), synesis is a Greek term derived from the verb synienai. This verb means "to send, to bring, or to set together," "to perceive," "to hear", and "to come to an understanding about something." From this definition, we can infer that the concept "synesis" always involves a communal and dialogical dimension (Long, 2002). One of the meanings of synesis established by Liddell and Scott is "conscience." For them, there is a link between synesis and syneidesis, a word that means: "a joint knowledge or consciousness," or "conscience":

"However, [synesis] is derived from a different root, namely, *synidein. This verb is linked to verbs of knowledge related to the sense of sight: synoran, 'to see together,' and syneidenai, 'to share in the knowledge' of a thing, or 'to be conscious' to oneself, (when used with the dative). Taken together, the cluster of words in which synesis is embedded clearly suggests that it connotes a sort of intelligence directed towards and intimately related to others. Thus, the translation offered here is designed to bring out this dimension of the term that is otherwise eclipsed when merely translated into English as 'intelligence' or 'understanding'." (Long, 2002: 58).

3. Hermeneutical perspectives and educational interpretations of synesis

Reading Aristotle's paragraph, one can conclude that synesis is different from phronesis. The former is a disposition, an intellectual dynamis (power), a capacity of nous (intellect). Which means that synesis is something referred to things that are subject to doubt and that make one be perplexed and reflective about them (Rowe & Broadie, 2002). To be clear, Aristotle states that synesis deals neither with metaphysical nor with physical things. As nous' capacity, synesis is one of its functions in opposition to dianoia (discourse).

Synesis is also linked to sophia, because: "the power of insight of understanding into the things that are subject to doubt, operates with opinion and not with the truth contained directly as in the case of sophia. For this reason, what is subject to doubt needs deliberation. By the power of design which it involves, synesis, still lies within the intellectual sphere, the link with action being accomplished by phronesis. Practical wisdom holds the urgency of decision as far as action is concerned." (Isai, 2013: 75).

From Aristotle's point of view, there exists a strict relationship betweenphronesis and synesis. Synesis is literally a "joining" or "meeting together", and it connotes a kind of being with others, and indicates the peculiar kind of intelligence exhibited by the phronimos, the wise man. The difference between phronesis and synesis is that whereas synesis is an intellectual capacity to judge, phronesis is a virtue able to bridge the gap between theoretical judgment and action (Zagal, 1999). For this reason:

"Phronesis is never a purely intellectual exercise, yet if the intellectual side of phronesis is permitted to be completely eclipsed, the misconception emerges that it is merely a matter of mechanical habituation. As will be seen in the discussion of phronesis and arete below, the disposition of phronesis is thoroughly saturated by deliberation. Here, however, he is concerned to establish precisely what sort of intellectual operation is at work in phronesis." (Long, 2002: 45).

When Aristotle says that synesis deals with things judged using doxa and phronesis, when someone else speaks (allou legontos) about them, it indicates that synesis in never pursued in isolation, but in dialogical encounters with others. In the line with this idea, Hans-Georg Gadamer has built a specific, very interesting and useful, from a pedagogical point of view, theory of synesis. Synesis is linked to syneidesis and conscience because:

"Once it is recognized as the sort of intelligence that is directed toward or exercised in conjunction with another, a more nuanced and indeed stronger translation of it may be suggested. The word itself has an etymological relation to 'syneidesis,' or 'conscience.' Thus, although 'syneidesis' never appears in Aristotle as such, and there remains in the term "conscience" dangerously misleading Christian theological and Heideggerian connotations, perhaps we can nonetheless risk the more bold translation of synesis as 'conscientious apprehension' so as to emphasize the ethical and dialogical connotations it clearly has in Aristotle." (Long, 2002: 46).

Synesis is "conscientious apprehension", and it has, as stated above, ethical and dialogical connotations. Long (2002), who studied the concept of synesis in Aristotle, says that:

"'Conscientious apprehension' names the ability to grasp the nature of a given situation in a mode of critical self-reflection that remains constantly conscious of the fact that the judge too is implicated in each act of judgment. The ability to imagine one's way into the position of the other and to listen as the other speaks (allou legontos) are important elements of conscientious apprehension because they disrupt the internal monologue of the phronimos and direct it towards that which is outside itself. Here phronesis is understood as dialogical not merely because it can listen as others speak, but also because it recognizes that the concrete situation itself is never exclusively determined by its subjective judgment. Indeed, the fact that synesis must operate with doxa and not, as sophia, with an immediate grasp of the truth, already suggests the extent to which phronesis is itself determined by the world in which it is embedded." (Long, 2002: 46).

Synesis is an important concept in Gadamer, because:

"Besidesphronesis, which Gadamer calls 'the virtue of judicious judgement', is synesis, the ability to understand. This form of understanding is different from the intellectual capacity to understand abstract notions or mathematical demonstrations. In this case, it is a form of understanding that comes from experience of similar events. Only the one who has gone through similar experiences can truly understand all the human things." (Isai, 2013: 75).

To be clear, synesis is a synienai, that is to say, it is a comprehending in order to make a decision; a comprehending others, learning from this experience, and making the better decision, deliberating in the interest of and to the advantage of them. Phronesis means to recognize what is universal into the particular: but it has many limits because it is an ethical attitude based on a moral disposition (a wise, virtuous and moral act) which is self-referential (it is always and only for me).

Therefore one can affirm that synesis has the capacity of improving and perfecting phronesis as wisdom. Phronesis has an epistemological duality. Reasoning from the point of view that conceives of pedagogy as a hermeneutical theoretical and practical science of education (Gallagher, 1992), one can say that phronesis knows the principals of its model (pedagogy) and knows how to apply them to praxis, to the concrete and practical case (education). Education is both synesis (comprehension and judgment) and phronesis (wise reasoning).

Education is (and always it requires) synesis, because education is a rapid penetration into the ethicality of the action, and it is a not discursive operation which can be analyzed. Synesis is sensitiveness, a capacity to see the ethicality of an action (Levin, 1972; Desideri, 1998). The need for synesis from education, it demonstrates that education, as a human practice, is never something fully rational. Like synesis, education is something that is between animal functions (sensitiveness) and intellectual virtues (techne and phronesis). So one can conclude that Education is both phronesis and synesis. Synesis is a way, a path, to phronesis; and synesis is a reflective component of phronesis, an exercise aimed at comprehending and helping the other.

On the basis of Gadamer's and Heidegger's translation of synesis, the correct meaning of this term would be given by the two following German words: Rücksicht ("regard", "consideration", "respect") and Verständnis ("comprehension"), which are intrinsically related to (Greek) terms like gnome (Einsicht in German, "judgment", "discernment") and sygnome (Nachsicht in German, "indulgence", "compliance") (Conill, 2006).

Synesis is a hermeneutical tool that every educator must own. Synesis is an attitude between techne (dianoetic virtue of poiesis and practical reason) and phronesis. For this reason, the educator, if she or he wants to educate well, must use the following hermeneutical tools: techne (which can be bad or good, and it serves as a knowledge of means); synesis (which is a way and a bridge to the other); and phronesis (which is a tool to know the relation between means and goals).

Synesis also relates to syneidesis, a term that literally means consciousness or awareness. Syneidesis (distinguished from synderesis) comes from the Greek verb syn-eidenai ("to know from an act of seeing and watching"), that is "to have knowledge/to be aware of something", and "to have the capacity to apply general principles of moral judgment to particular cases." In this sense, synesis is a conscience that comes from an act of "hearing", "listening", "comprehending", "understanding", "taking care of the other, watching her/him carefully and

in depth", and the like (Osborne, 1931; Snell, 1953).

One could say that synesis is the conscience that listens to itself, and to its human roots; synesis is our conscience that listens to, understands, and recognizes the other as a human being (Franco, 2000). Educator's knowledge thus can be regarded as phronetic and synetic at the same time.

1) Educators' knowledge is phronetic because it refers to a knowledge-for-itself, a wisdom that starts from the ethical perception of educational situation as a state-of-our-actions, and then as a state-to-us; situation in which we act, and in which we are called in person to make a decision about what is right or wrong to do for us. This knowledge constitutes a clear understanding of ourselves and of our capacity and potential in terms of actions and behaviours in different situations. It is a technical knowledge (a know-how), which is external and lacks an internal dimension, namely, that one of consciousness; it is a well doing that also needs an equitable and fair acting (which is given by epieikeia, that is "equity").

2) Educators' knowledge is synetic because it refers to a knowledge-for-the-other and implies a capacity to assess and to understand her/his situation. This is done not only in technical terms (through the knowledge of sciences, for example), but rather in terms of human comprehension (that is in terms of sympatheia and empatheia). This human comprehension gives educators the possibility to judge fairly and to contribute with their actions (with a good advice, for example) to the development and improvement of the other as a person by assuming a human responsibility (developed through a specific and personal consciousness as educator) before him/her (Gadamer, 1996a).

These two types of knowledge are fundamental hermeneutic tools to empower both teachers and educators by providing them with the capacity to understand the different types of educational situations they face in their everyday professional life.

To sum up, being a teacher or an educator, understood as figures located between the ethical-normative dimension of education as theory and its methodological-didactical dimension as practice, always requires the deep development of skills related to the type of knowledge defined as "synetic" in this study. The two types of knowledge mentioned above highlight how education always requires decision-making processes related not only to judging and assigning values, but also to taking care of the other.

Teachers and educators, in fact, have the duty to not only judge (according to what is right or wrong in terms of rules, ethics, traditions, behaviours), her/his students; but also in terms of care, commitment, interest and attention to their growth as subjects of ethics and morality: that is to say, in terms of subject-persons. The knowledge of the teacher and educator, as a synetic understanding and awareness, appears in all respects as a knowledge of care in which the consciousness of the other as person, and the respect devoted to her/him is the only fundamental criterion for acting.

Every educational situation implies a wide range of emotions, feelings and passions related to an ethical and moral sphere. This type of situation requires both a synetic and phronetic attitude. From this standpoint, synesis, as an understanding and awareness of the other, represents the hearth of education. What gives sense to education and to the complex set of values and actions implied in it, is the will and willingness to participate through an aware action aimed at helping and improving the other as a human being, and at continuously taking care of her/him in the situations that she/he is experiencing. Education implies rational actions, but it is also refers to states linked to the sphere of emotions and feelings. One has not to forget that the assessment and evaluation by the teacher is always

deeply embedded in a dimension that links her/him to synesis.

4. Synesis as theory and practice of education

For the above mentioned reasons, synesis represents a fundamental concept to be analyzed in the fields of epistemology and philosophy of education. Therefore, one can affirm that synesis is what can be defined as the departure and arrival of education, because it implies the concept of responsibility conceived of as taking care and being interested in the other, and in her/his development as a human and social being.

In a nutshell, synesis sums up the actions of caring and acting with those of responsibility and awareness of the other that education as a human practice implies. One could say that synesis activates the circle of human care, a process in which education represents a fundamental aspect. In contemporary philosophy of education, phronesis is identified with practical reason, with a knowledge that directs and guides the teacher or educator's actions so that she/he can perform in the best possible way while teaching or educating. To sum up, both educators and teachers must always act and behave by using synesis; according to the Aristotelian principle of the epieikeia (equity and fairness) and to synesis interpreted as the faculty of "apprehension", "right judgement", "understanding, intelligence", and "conscience" (Gadamer, 1996). Synesis must be considered as a fundamental component in the theory and practice of education, and be thought of as strictly connected to phronesis.

Actually, synesis and phronesis show that education always implies the three following main dimensions:

1) an ontological dimension which deals with Being and its values, and gives sense to education as a human and transcendental practice;

2) a technical dimension which refers to the application of a system of rules to interpret and to judge the other, and to put into practice, in the best way, all the values that education implies;

3) a deontological dimension concerning why and with what purpose we educate or teach in order to help people acknowledge their responsibility and commitment as social agents to a better world.

To be clear, education not only implies, phronesis ("technical competence" and "wisdom" in interpreting and understanding other's situation by applying a pedagogical models), and synesis ("awareness" of others, "comprehension" of their situations in the human perspective of care, help, and "good advice" for their improvement as persons). Rather, it also implies epieikeia: that is, the principle of "equity" that enables teachers and educators to apply, in a practical way, the rules of education in accordance with a pedagogical consciousness (Isidori, 2005). In a nutshell, synesis, phronesis, and epieikeia are the three main principles of educational practice.

Equality and fairness, in fact, facilitate the practical application of rules when the teacher or educator must make a decision applying the principles of a pedagogical model. Teachers and educators, through synesis and epieikeia, act as impartial judges with moderation and flexibility when they do it according to that category of equity that, as pointed out by the philosopher Hans Gadamer (2004), allows the application of the rules to a practical case in a flexible and no rigid way.

5. Conclusion

Synesis, phronesis, and epieikeia make teachers and educators capable to reason and act in a coherent way, and out of fixed patterns. Synesis helps the educator and teacher, through fairness and common sense, to adapt the abstract world of the values and principles of education to the concrete situations of people. This happens because the teacher and educator are always communicators able to mediate, and they must show qualities and capabilities derived from practical wisdom, responsibility, and consciousness of the other as human being (this knowledge is the result of a fusion between phronesis and synesis).

These qualities can be summed up in the concept of "balance" that every educator or teacher should have. This balance, seen from the perspective of educational hermeneutics and pedagogy, implies moderation, and involves calm, patience, impartiality, tolerance, understanding and openness towards others.

Educational practice always requires a hermeneutic sensitiveness as well as specific synetic attitudes, skills, and qualities from the teacher/educator, who must be able to interpret and understand the other. All these skills can be gained and developed only by a continuous hermeneutical exercise of interpretation-understanding of other human beings. To conclude, it is only this willingness and openness to the phronetic and synetic wisdom based on equity-epieikeia which allows educational practice to develop as a democratic and a fair complex set of actions without falling into contradictions and paradoxes.

References

Aristotle (2004). Nicomachean Ethics. Translated and edited by R. Crisp. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Conill, J. (2006). Ética hermenéutica. Critica desde la facticidad: Tecnos: Madrid.

Desideri, F. (1998). L 'ascolto della coscienza: una ricerca filosofica. Milano: Feltrinelli Editore.

Franco, A. (2000). Immagine, senso, ermeneutica. Napoli: Guida.

Gadamer, H. G. (1996a). Le problème de la conscience historique. Paris: Seuil.

Gadamer, H. G. (1996b). The enigma of health: The art oof healing in a scientific age. Cambridge: Polity Press. Gadamer, H. G. (2004). Truth and Method. New York, NY: Bloomsbury Publishing. Gallagher, S. (1992). Hermeneutics and education. SUNY Press: New York.

Isai, M. D. (2013). Phronesis Between Ethics And Ontology. Philosophia. Studia Universitatis Babes-Bolyai, 58 (2), 69-84. Isidori, E. (2005). Ermeneutica e pedagogia della persona. Dal dialogo alla cura. Roma: Aracne.

Levin, F. R. (1972). Synesis in Aristoxenian theory. In Transactions of the American Philological Association (pp. 211-234). Case Western Reserve University.

Liddell, H. G., & Scott, R. (1996). A Greek-English lexicon: with a revised supplement. H. S. Jones (Ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Long, C. P. (2002). The ontological reappropriation of phronesis. Continental Philosophy Review, 35(1), 35-60.

Osborne, H. (1931). Synesis and syneidesis. The Classical Review, 45 (1), 8-10.

Rowe, C. J., & Broadie, S. (2002) (Eds). Nicomachean ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Snell, B. (1953). The Discovery of the Mind. The Greek Origins of European Thought. Translated by T.G Rosenmeyer. Oxford: Blackwell. Zagal, H. (1999). Synesis, euphya y anchinoia en Aristoteles. Algunas habilidades para el conocimiento del singular. Anuario filosofico, 32(1), 129-145.